A quick comment on Chief Justice John Roberts’s concurrence in Dobbs. As many expected from oral argument (including me) and leaks of the deliberation in May, Chief Justice Roberts sought in vain for a middle ground that would uphold the Mississippi law banning abortion after fifteen weeks with certain exceptions, but that would not overrule the basic right to an abortion found in Roe and Casey. Roberts’s concurrence in the judgment stuck to his lonely compromise position. I hoped that Roberts might at least offer some basis for why a fifteen-week ban would be permissible without a wholesale review of Roe.
Continue reading “John Roberts’s Dobbs opinion: discretion, restraint, rules”Category: Uncategorized
Book Launch Cornucopia
The book launch for Common Good Constitutionalism took place last Thursday evening at the National Press Club. The run of show went as follows: (1) an introduction by Sohrab Ahmari; (2) my talk; (3) in-person responses from Judge Paul Matey, Jeff Wall, and Professor Patrick Deneen; (4) on video, a response from Judge Amul Thapar, who was unfortunately unable to attend in person; and (5) some thoughts by me in reply to each of the respondents. Unfortunately the program ran a bit long, so time did not permit questions from the audience. The program as a whole featured a genuine diversity of views, with Jeff Wall taking a rather libertarian perspective and Judge Thapar an originalist one.
This post includes, in order: (1) my written talk, which as inevitably occurs, differs slightly from the actual delivery; (2) an audio recording of the whole proceeding (barring a few words cut off at the beginning of Sohrab Ahmari’s introduction); (3) Judge Thapar’s video, posted separately because the audio quality of the recording of the whole may make it difficult for the listener to hear his remarks; (4) a written version of my reply to Judge Thapar in particular, again differing slightly from the actual delivery, and posted separately to make the discussion of Aquinas more accessible.
Please bear in mind that this was not a strictly academic event. These materials are informal and are posted in the hopes of advancing the debate. Enjoy! Continue reading “Book Launch Cornucopia”
Second thoughts about a first look
The leak of Justice Samuel Alito’s draft opinion in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization is unprecedented. The mere fact of the leak is unprecedented, though perhaps not surprising since ready access to abortion has become something more than a legal question to many lawyers, activists, and politicians. Norms, no matter how cherished or long held, yield in emergencies, and one suspects that a certain kind of advocate believes this is an emergency. Scarcely less shocking than the leak, however, is the fact that the draft opinion itself indicates, at least as a preliminary matter, that there are five votes to overturn Roe v. Wade and Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, the twin pillars of the legal abortion regime in the United States.
Justice Alito’s draft was dated (at least for the purposes of circulation) February 10, 2022 and is marked “1st Draft.” Considering that Dobbs was argued at the beginning of December 2021 and the conference on the case held shortly thereafter, I think it is safe to assume that it represents a fairly early draft of the opinion, written before concurrences and dissents were circulated. The Dobbs opinion probably has developed in some dimensions since February 10. Nevertheless, one imagines that the broad outlines of the opinion will remain substantially the same, barring a change in votes or some other exigency. It is only slightly premature, I think, to conduct a close analysis of the Dobbs draft as though it were the opinion of the Court.
Continue reading “Second thoughts about a first look”No Fence to Sit On
I had been working on a post addressing a new abortion policy bill in Connecticut, which is headed to the governor’s desk for signature sometime this week, when Politico published the leaked first draft of Justice Alito’s opinion last night. Regarding that news, I will make only two comments. First, while it reflects a final holding (overruling Roe) that I believe most if not all contributors to I&I support, any opinion is not official until promulgated by the Court itself, and I’m not going to comment on its substance. Second, the leak should be seen for what it is—an attempt to interfere with the normal processes of an institution and to galvanize public opinion and legislative and executive officials. The leak should be investigated and the individual sanctioned appropriately.
Nevertheless, the public reaction to the draft opinion was predictable in the emotional response it has generated and the calls for court-packing, impeachment, and other politically punitive actions. That reaction points to a key conclusion—once Roe nationalized abortion policy, there is no easy way for the Court to extract itself from that issue. The great twentieth century American moral philosopher Johnny Cash once said, “How well I have learned that there is no fence to sit on between heaven and hell. There is a deep, wide gulf, a chasm, and in that chasm is no place for any man.” A final decision returning abortion policy to the states is not the end—as Connecticut shows, it is only the beginning of a new phase.
Continue reading “No Fence to Sit On”Pickwickian Originalism
We offer here a very few thoughts — essentially, only one thought — about a recent argument for a kind of generic originalism. The argument was published by Joel Alicea, a law professor at the Catholic University of America, in a draft paper titled “The Moral Authority of Original Meaning.”[1] Given that the paper claims to ground its argument in the classical legal tradition; that it has been heavily promoted by the quasi-official organs of legal originalism, such as the National Review and the Legal Theory Blog; and that the paper is, if nothing else, strikingly ambitious, a brief response seems warranted.
Continue reading “Pickwickian Originalism”Judicial Interpretation and Dirty Words: An Analysis of Iancu v. Brunetti
This is the second of a series on the common good and trademark law examining the case of Iancu v. Brunetti. The first post may be found here.
Professor Adrian Vermeule, my fellow contributor here at Ius et Iustitium, has recently published a concise and convincing book expounding on common good constitutionalism. Near the beginning he states that his goal is to present an “interpretive” argument, that is, to show that law in general, and American law in particular, functions best “when the courts defer to public determination of [positive legal provisions], so long as the public authority acts rationally and with a view to legitimate public purposes.” For the meat of this interpretive argument, Vermeule turns to several different famous and important cases, including two Supreme Court cases: Lochner v. New York and United States v. Curtiss-Wright Export Corp.
At the risk of a bit too much levity, I would like to extend and apply Vermeule’s interpretive argument to a much less important Supreme Court case—whether the word FUCT should have been granted trademark registration or barred as “immoral or scandalous.” My first post on trademarks discussed the case of Iancu v. Brunetti, which poses a straightforward matter for decision. Erik Brunetti wanted to register the use of the mark FUCT for shirts and other apparel. Section 2(a) of the Lanham Act of 1946 prohibits registration marks that are, among other bars, “immoral or scandalous.” Brunetti asserted such a prohibition ran afoul of the First Amendment. My first post addressed the background of the case and presented it in the context of the purpose of trademark law.
Today, I turn to the justices’ opinions. This would seem to be a straightforward case, yet Brunetti resulted in a 6-3 decision, with 5 different opinions sparring over issues of statutory interpretation, constitutional interpretation, deference, and governmental abuse of power. Seemingly mundane cases can be more illuminating of justices’ legal analysis and interpretative methods. Through Brunetti, I hope to address one criticism that has been brought against Vermeule’s argument—that natural law and originalism will ultimately come to the same conclusion in most cases regarding the application of moral principles to the law. It turns out that the “Case of the FUCT Registration” proves that natural lawyers and originalists do indeed arrive at different substantive results.
Textualism in the Service of Legal Progressivism: Kagan’s Majority Opinion in Brunetti
Justice Kagan is widely recognized as a great legal writer, and her concise and clear majority opinion in Brunetti is no exception. Joined by justices across the spectrum—Ginsburg, Kavanaugh, Gorsuch, Thomas, and Alito (with a short concurrence)—Kagan’s opinion steps through the now de rigeur First Amendment analysis. First, is the statute content- or viewpoint-based, or is it viewpoint-neutral? If the statute regulates speech based on its content, then it is “presumptively unconstitutional” unless the speech in question is within one of a narrow range of exceptions (fraudulent speech, fighting words, imminent threats, obscenity, etc.). If the statute is viewpoint neutral, it will be judged on whether the restriction is reasonably tailored to meet legitimate government ends.
Kagan finds that the statute is viewpoint-based. Admittedly, it is difficult to plausibly suggest otherwise. The statute bans marks that are “immoral or scandalous,” which requires a specific judgment on the content of the words forming the trademark. Justice Kagan noted, for example, that the USPTO had rejected marks that promoted drug use (MARIJUANA COLA), promoted terrorism (BABY AL QAEDA), or could be deemed blasphemous (MADONNA on wine), while marks that opposed drug use, related to the War on Terror Memorial, or indicated positive connotations of faith were granted registration.
Kagan does find that the words “immoral or scandalous” are broad and open to various meanings, so one may ask why the Court does not simply interpret the words narrowly? Kagan answers this question by demonstrating her commitment to her famous 2015 quip, “We are all textualists now.” “This Court,” she writes, “may interpret ambiguous statutory language to avoid serious constitutional doubts, … [b]ut that canon of construction applies only when ambiguity exists.” The “scandalous or immoral” bar applies not just to lewd, sexually explicit, or profane marks (which the government offered as narrowing constructions), but rather to “the universe of immoral or scandalous material.” Since the statute could not be saved by a narrower construction, it was declared unconstitutional.
We should pause here to consider some historical background. When Congress passed the Lanham Act in 1946 there was no question that it believed it could properly bar “immoral or scandalous” marks from registration. The bar itself dates back to the 1905 Trademarks Act Section 5(a), using exactly the same language. Throughout this time, as a recent Harvard Law Review note states, blasphemy laws and other restrictions on immoral or scandalous speech were routinely upheld as constitutional. Just five years before passage of the Lanham Act, the Tenth Circuit upheld an Oklahoma City ordinance that imposed a fine for “casting contumelious reproach or profane ridicule on God.” Oney v. Oklahoma City, 120 F.2d 861, 865 (10th Cir. 1941). If cities could criminally punish pure speech that was blasphemous, surely Congress reasonably assumed it could simply deny government benefits to trademarks (speech that serves a communal, market-protecting function) that are immoral or scandalous. If cities could implement statutes using words such as “contumelious reproach” and “profane ridicule,” the potential ambiguity or breadth in “immoral or scandalous” seems tame by comparison.
Yet Kagan strikes down the law, using the tiered scrutiny system that only became commonly used and described during the postwar Warren and Burger courts. (Cohen v. California, the case of Paul Cohen’s “Fuck the Draft” jacket, was decided in 1971.) So why does the Court effectively fault Congress for failing to foresee a revolutionary shift in constitutional interpretation? Couldn’t the Court simply adopt Congress’ intent or purpose and narrowly construe the statute?
Kagan rejects the narrowing interpretation because that postwar legal revolution marks the way of legal progressivism, which Vermeule writes “is rooted in a particular mythology of endless liberation through the continual overcoming of the reactionary past.” Not punishing men wearing vulgar jackets, or not refusing to grant trademark protection even to vulgar marks, is proof for Kagan of our commitment to “liberal values.” The tiered scrutiny system is intended to drain analysis of speech content from the law despite the fact that for over 150 years, the First Amendment was not understood to require such emptying. For a progressive jurisprudence, there is no need to overturn that system.
So, how do the four more moderate or conservative justices get reeled in by Kagan and Ginsburg here? Textualism is her bait. The statute says what it says, Kagan writes, and we cannot do otherwise. We have access to dictionaries, we know what these words mean, and they are broad definitions and viewpoint-based. The entire tone of Kagan’s majority opinion conveys a sense of, “There’s nothing to see here.” We’re not changing constitutional interpretations to which conservatives acquiesced decades ago, and we’re not doing anything but defining words and putting them in the appropriate box. Move along. In many ways, this tone is similar to the most famous recent example of textualism serving to advance progressive goals: Justice Gorsuch’s decision in Bostock finding that Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 applies to discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation and gender identity.
Textualism as a Hindrance to Traditional Legal Interpretation: Alito’s Concurrence
But even if conservative justices would be more interested in preventing immoral or scandalous marks from being granted benefits under trademark law, Justice Alito’s concurrence demonstrates how they nevertheless play along. Textualism is simply principled adherence to the text, and it’s too bad Congress drafted the law using the wrong magic words. But the Court can’t rewrite statutes, and in Alito’s view, “a law banning speech deemed by government officials to be ‘immoral’ or ‘scandalous’ can easily be exploited for illegitimate ends.” As Vermeule notes in Common Good Constitutionalism, worries about abuse of power are always directed to government officials. Legal conservatives are myopically unable to see abuse of the common good by private actors with the same level of urgency. And among potential governmental abuses of power, I hope that rogue trademark examining attorneys, nefariously and selectively deploying their powers to deny protection to arguably naughty trademarks, are not high on the list of severe abuses of power. In essence, we see in Alito’s opinion a deep suspicion of government action as ever being conducive to the common good, and Congress and agencies should be given no deference.
In any case, Alito’s short concurrence demonstrates how textualism is used by conservatives as a screen for “principled decisionmaking,” when in fact it is simply a failure to live up to the consequences of their failure to judge. “Our decision does not prevent Congress from adopting a more carefully focused statute that precludes the registration of marks containing vulgar terms that play no real part in the expression of ideas,” Alito writes, suggesting Congress just needs to write a better statute. What words would Alito use? Vulgar? Shocking? Offensive? These are of course dictionary synonyms for “scandalous,” which he just agreed was unconstitutionally broad. Like Gorsuch’s twisted interpretation of Title VII in Bostock, a wooden textualism such as Alito’s would render impossible any Congressional attempt to rewrite the statute to cover what it plainly intended to at the time of enactment.
Here, too, is an exemplary instance of the Court’s foremost originalists arriving at a decision that is at odds with common good jurisprudence. The common good, as discussed below, would simply ask whether Congress has reasonably determined a rule to promote stated public purposes. In contrast, the originalists here ignore the original public meaning and purpose behind the words “immoral and scandalous” when they were enacted in 1905 and reenacted in 1946, at a time when the jurisprudential landscape was very different. And they ignore that the Founding Fathers almost certainly did not understand the First Amendment to apply to commercial speech (as statutes about public decorum and regulation of trade in the 18th century common market attest). Rather they take statutes out of context, apply a modern interpretation of the First Amendment, and arrive at a conclusion that Alito seems to detest but does nothing to resolve. Brunetti may be a somewhat silly case, but it is exemplary of the kind of reasoning that conservatives have come to fear from originalists on the Court in more impactful cases.
Complicating Textualism: Sotomayor’s and Roberts’ Dissents
Each of the dissenting justices—Sotomayor, Breyer, and Roberts—agreed with the majority that the bar on “immoral” marks fell as viewpoint based. They differed in that they believed the bar on “scandalous” marks could be independently salvaged. Justice Sotomayor’s dissent was joined by Breyer, who also wrote a separate dissent addressed below. She walks through a standard textualist rejoinder to the majority, stating first that the term was ambiguous and that a reasonable limiting construction would be to apply “scandalous” to obscene, vulgar, or profane marks. She then walks through the intermediate scrutiny analysis to arrive at the conclusion that such a construction would be constitutional. For reasons he does not make clear, Roberts does not formally join Sotomayor’s dissent, but he states that he agrees with Justice Sotomayor’s narrowing construction in his own four-paragraph dissent.
For our purposes, the most important part of each of their dissents is the pains taken to make two points. First, everyone denies that the government is making or can make any moral judgment when denying trademarks. No justice suggests that the government could deny registration simply on the basis of immorality. Second, they both reiterate that no one is actually being prevented from speaking; the government is simply choosing not to confer a benefit. Sotomayor writes, “the First Amendment protects Brunetti’s right to use words like the one at issue here,” while Roberts concludes, “the First Amendment protects freedom of speech;” it’s simply that the Government is not required to “give aid and comfort to those using obscene, vulgar, and profane modes of expression.” Sotomayor’s and Roberts’ dissents demonstrate that, even in losing, they are still playing by the rules of modern progressive and originalist jurisprudence. For those seeking to reconnect the law to the general welfare and the common good, that’s a losing game.
A Halfway Attempt at a Common Good Opinion: Breyer’s Dissent
I finally turn to Breyer’s dissent, the most interesting opinion of the quintet. He astutely notes that the provision in question, which grants a government benefit to certain private activity, does not easily fit into any of the usual categories of First Amendment speech. Picking up a point I raised in my first post on this case, he dismisses the idea that trademarks are “commercial speech” because they serve a “commercial function” to identify a product’s source. He adds that offensive and vulgar words are specifically used to attract attention and to emotionally provoke viewers and listeners, which also affects the function of the market.
Rather than sticking to the usual First Amendment playbook of asking whether the statute is viewpoint based or neutral and then applying the appropriate tier of scrutiny, Breyer “would appeal more often and more directly to the values the First Amendment seeks to protect.” Ultimately, he asks whether the provision in question “works speech-related harm that is out of proportion to its justifications.” Breyer concludes that the limited harm to speech in such a case is outweighed by the government’s decision to regulate speech in commercial contexts to protect the function of the market, especially in cases where children may be present.
In so many words—and in his characteristically Breyeresque attempt to formulate a multi-factor balancing test—Breyer is getting to a key point. Does the government have legitimate reasons to prevent the use of scandalous marks? Yes. Did Congress draw a reasonable line? Yes. Does that line harm core First Amendment values? No. Then the court should defer to Congress.
This is reminiscent of Justice Harlan’s opinion in Mugler v. Kansas and his dissent in Lochner, which Vermeule highlighted here and in his book as model opinions of common good constitutionalism. Of course the state can make reasonable laws directed to the common good, and a bar on scandalous marks is such a reasonable statute. Unlike Alito, Breyer would defer to decisions by Congress and the agency applying the statute, however imperfect such application may be.
My only complaint here is that Breyer does not go far enough—the same analysis should apply to the immorality bar as to the scandal bar.
A Hypothetical Common Good Opinion in Brunetti
How might such an opinion be structured? First, the opinion would recognize that the government and courts themselves have permitted decisions based on moral conclusions before. The multiple examples of blasphemy laws cited above are one line of cases, but we need not even leave the realm of intellectual property law. As I have described with respect to patents, Justice Story understood the utility requirement to prohibit patents being granted to “mischievous or immoral” inventions, setting up a line of precedent that lasted until 1936. Indeed, a decision to deny patent protection, like denial of a trademark registration, is not a bar against use of the invention itself but rather simply a denial of governmental benefit. (In fact, not even the Supreme Court or the Federal Circuit has suggested that Justice Story’s moral gloss on the utility requirement is unconstitutional—just that it does not apply under the current patent statute.)
Second, the court opinion would recognize that Congress is acting within its sphere of competency. It is within the powers of Congress to regulate interstate commerce, including the tenor and civility of that commerce. Furthermore, Congress has specifically granted the Patent & Trademark Office the faculty to make those decisions on a case-by-case basis.
Third, Congress may act on a reasonable conception of the common good in that sphere. As Justice Breyer writes, Congress may act to ensure that the marketplace remains a place of common courtesy, particularly in the case of trademarks that serve an important role in the functioning of the market.
Finally, reasonable and nonarbitrary decisions by a trademark examining attorney would be upheld. This is where Alito’s concerns about abuse of power really fall apart. Denial of trademark registration is not a matter of urgency, and courts can review any decision to deny for arbitrariness. But both immorality and scandal in the common marketplace are reasonable bases for Congress to deny government benefits. Assuming the decision is reasonable in a particular case, courts should then defer.
In short, the public authority may act for the common good, including the promotion of health, safety, and morals in the commons. It does so by making reasonable determinations about the means to promote its stated public purposes, namely, that immoral and scandalous marks should not receive government protection. In such cases judges must defer. A simple enough summary—one Vermeule himself would recognize. For a conservative in the common good tradition, this is an exceptionally easy case, and we should wonder why the originalists on the Court strive so hard to obtain the wrong result.
Dante’s Lawyers from Purgatory: Trajan
2021 marked the 700 th anniversary of Dante’s death and saw the publication on March 25 of Pope Francis’ Candor Lucis Aeterna, a lucid analysis of Dante and his work. This is the third of a series of Ius et Iustitium pieces by Aníbal Sabater discussing lawyers in the Divine Comedy. The first two pieces, “Dante’s Lawyers from Hell” and “Dante’s Lawyers from Purgatory: Cato” can be found here.
Man becomes proud, Aquinas reminds us, not only by coveting God’s likeness or human praise, but also by indulging in “excellence,” that is, in the presumption of superiority over others.[1] This notion that there is spiritual danger in being too good at anything—including a professional activity—permeates the Commedia[2] and gets special attention in Purgatorio, where the haughty are purified by carrying heavy stones while contemplating three animated sculptures.[3] The first is a statue of Our Lady uttering her “Ecce Ancilla Domini”;[4] the second shows David dancing merrily before the Ark, indifferent to his wife, Michol, who mocks him for this “un-royal” conduct; the third depicts the encounter between a widow and the Roman Emperor Trajan, as he departs for the Dacian Wars. She asks him to judge his son’s assassins. Trajan demurs, but she insists and eventually persuades him.[5]
Continue reading “Dante’s Lawyers from Purgatory: Trajan”Originalist Blasphemy
Ius & Iustitium is pleased to present this guest post from T.A.D., a third-year student at Harvard Law School.
If today the government tried to ban blasphemy – the offense of maliciously reviling God or Christianity – it would face a constitutional hurdle. More precisely, it would face three hurdles: the Free Speech Clause, Free Exercise Clause, and Establishment Clause of the First Amendment. Based on the way that many people now understand these constitutional provisions, the government could face an uphill legal battle in proscribing blasphemy.
But in a recently published Harvard Law Review piece, I argue that the original meaning of free speech, religious freedom, and non-establishment was different. As originally understood, these constitutional guarantees did not prevent the government from punishing blasphemy. In other words, even when the government was constitutionally forbidden from abridging free speech, prohibiting free religious exercise, or recognizing any religious establishment, it could still criminalize blasphemy.
Continue reading “Originalist Blasphemy”Blessed Rosario Livatino: In Service to the Common Good
On May 9, 2021, Rosario Livatino, a magistrate little known outside of Italy, was beatified. In the basilica cathedral of Agrigento in Sicily, the faithful venerated the bloodied shirt worn by Blessed Rosario during the moment of his horrific murder by the Stidda, a rival gang of the more famous Sicilian Mafia. In Rome, Pope Francis commented, “In his service to the common good, as an exemplary judge who never succumbed to corruption, he sought to judge not to condemn but to redeem . . . . His work placed him firmly under the protection of God. For this reason, he became a witness to the Gospel even unto a heroic death.”
People outside of Italy might imagine that the violent mob murder of a magistrate perhaps occurred in the time of Al Capone, of tommy guns, and Prohibition. However, Blessed Rosario was gunned down off the side of a highway in Sicily on the morning of September 21, 1990, a date firmly within the lifetime of most adults. Whereas in the United States mob violence is viewed as distant history or associated with popular films or television shows, for the people of Sicily this was the reality of recent memory, in which the brutal mafia wars blurred the lines between gangland violence and terrorism.
Blessed Rosario Livatino was born on October 3, 1952, in the small town of Canicattì, in the province of Agrigento. In 1975, he completed his law degree in Palermo. On the top of his thesis, he wrote three letters: STD, or Sub Tutela Dei. Thus, from the very beginning of his legal career Blessed Rosario entrusted his work as a lawyer and judge to God.
Over the course of his legal career, Blessed Rosario progressed from prosecutor to magistrate. His colleagues recall his rigorous and inflexible application of the law, while at the same time his ability to recognize the humanity in even the most hardened criminals. He understood that there was great disorganization and corruption in the region resulting in ineffectual and fragmented investigations. Blessed Rosario’s requests for greater coordination among law enforcement resulted in the closure of a local bank considered to be the safe deposit box for the mafia. These efforts resulted in the increase of threats against Blessed Rosario and his family. However, he was not swayed. Strengthened by his Catholic faith, he hungered for justice.
Only days before his thirty-eighth birthday, Blessed Rosario drove alone to the courthouse to begin his day of work, having refused an armed escort. Stidda assassins drove his vehicle off the road and Blessed Rosario was gunned down. In the investigation that followed, the perpetrators testified that they had committed their heinous crime because Blessed Rosario was immune to corruption. The mafiosi mocked Blessed Rosario’s Catholic faith and revealed that they had originally planned to murder him leaving the church where he daily adored the Blessed Sacrament. This was truly a murder in odium fidei. It is therefore not surprising that on the same day as Blessed Rosario’s beatification, the Vatican Dicastery for the Promotion of Integral Human Development announced the establishment of a working group committed to the excommunication of mafia members.
Blessed Rosario did not separate his life as a Catholic from his role as a lawyer or magistrate, though he lived his faith in humility. Every day he could be found at Mass, and in adoration before the Blessed Sacrament. This life of prayer and devotion provided him with the strength that enabled him to resist societal pressures and the temptation of lucrative corruption in order to take action for justice, and to root out the evil poisoning his beloved home. His was not a faith segregated to a private sphere, but rather his animating force, the light of Christ guiding him on the path of justice as a humble servant of the common good.
Catholic Constitutionalism: A Primer
What follows is a short talk I gave to students and young professionals from the Harvard-area community on the subject of “Catholic Constitutionalism.” It is intended merely a a brief primer and introduction to the issues, not as a comprehensive or theoretically sophisticated treatment. I nonetheless hope it is useful within its limits.
My talk today will be on Catholic Constitutionalism. (At a certain point, I will deliberately begin referring to this as “Catholic constitutionalism” with a small “c,” for reasons I will explain). One of my central questions will be whether there even is such a thing as Catholic Constitutionalism, to which I will answer: both no and yes. There is a sense in which there isn’t any such thing, and a sense in which there definitely is.
It won’t be a long talk, but it will have several different branches, so let me begin with a brief overview.
First I will say a bit about the Catholic doctrine as to the constitution of the temporal power. By constitution, I will always mean a small-c constitution in the classical sense, that is the total set of fundamental institutional and customary arrangements that structure public authority in a society. These may or may not be embodied in a large-C “Constitution” in the modern sense, which is a single unitary written document that purports to lay forth the fundamental institutions in a text. In the classical sense, there is very much such a thing as the British constitution, although there is no single British Constitution in the modern sense. That is, the British constitution is often called an unwritten constitution, although a more accurate description is that it is an uncodified constitution. It is composed of a number of fundamental statutes that have constitutional force, like the Act of Union 1707, of foundational constitutional principles (“What the Queen in Parliament enacts is law”), and also of fundamental unwritten normative customs or as the British call them “conventions.” All this was true of the Roman constitution as well.
The Savoyard constitutional theorist Joseph De Maistre went further, in his Essay on the Generative Principle of Constitutions, and argued that there is in a sense no such thing as a written constitution. Constitutions are begotten, not made; grown, not engineered. On this view, although of course there are written things that purport to be constitutions, they at most restate antecedent unwritten law, and are not causally efficacious in structuring the small-c constitution — the actual operating rules and norms of a political order. We need not accept or reject De Maistre‘s argument for present purposes, however.
Secondly, I will turn to the constitution of the Church founded by Our Lord, known in one of its major branches as the Roman Catholic Church. Here I will not speak to the department of theology known as ecclesiology, according to which the Church is the mystical body of Christ. I’ll leave that to others who know far more theology than I do. I will simply offer a few remarks about the Church’s outward-facing fundamental institutional arrangements.
I should clarify another term here. When I refer to “the Church’s institutional arrangements,” I mean the institutional setup of the spiritual power. Properly speaking and more accurately, however, “the Church” encompasses both clergy and laity, both the spiritual and the temporal power. Indeed Catholic theology has always recognized a sphere within which the temporal power has legitimate autonomy to govern according to the virtue of prudence, directed to proper ends. One must not confuse or conflate (although many do) Catholic doctrine with Caesaro-Papism or heirocratic rule, both of which fuse the spiritual and temporal powers in different ways, either fully subjecting the spiritual to the temporal, or the temporal to the spiritual. That is not the Catholic view. The Catholic view is “Duo Sunt,” in the famous words of Pope St. Gelasius—there are two powers that rule, the spiritual and the temporal power, and one of the major issues of political theology is to get them into the right relationship. Here we have the issue of so-called integralism, better known as political Catholicism or simply, as Dignitatis Humanae described it, “the traditional Catholic doctrine on the moral duty of men and societies toward the true religion and toward the one Church of Christ.” I mention this just for purposes of mapping the intellectual landscape, but integralism is not my subject today.
Third and finally, I’ll very briefly address the much-discussed question whether Catholic constitutionalism is compatible with liberalism, appropriately defined.