Shareholder Capitalism, Corporate Governance, and the Common Good: A UK Perspective

Ius & Iustitium welcomes submissions from academics, practicing lawyers, and students interested in the classical legal tradition. J.S. Liptrap is Assistant Professor, Law Department, University of Sussex; Research Associate, Centre for Business Research, Cambridge Judge Business School. The author adds: “Subject to the usual caveats, thanks to Conor Casey, Michael Foran and Adrian Vermeule for helpful discussions on an earlier draft of this essay.”


Introduction 

This essay, based upon an ongoing project, is the first in a two-part contribution that (i) critiques shareholder capitalism on classical legal grounds and then (ii) provides a preliminary sketch of what the UK corporate governance system would look like if it were more closely anchored in the classical legal tradition. Before delving into the first part of the project, though, a brief remark on academic humility is in order. The classical legal tradition has an ancient pedigree, and it has enjoyed something of a resurgence in recent memory and contemporary debates thanks to the labors of many commentators, some of whom were kind enough to discuss this project’s overall aims and direction of travel. Their contributions are mainly confined to constitutional and public law spheres, and my task, such as it is, is to adapt that body of work to the corporate governance field.[1] Hence, it is only right to acknowledge that intellectual debt at the outset. With that said, the impetus for the project is that there are perhaps myriad orthodox ways to critique shareholder capitalism, but they do not pierce the heart of the problem. When we shine a spotlight on the root problem with shareholder capitalism, referencing the classical legal traditional positions us to understand why reforms are actually necessary.  

Orthodox Critiques of Shareholder Capitalism

Shareholder capitalism, loosely, is a form of capitalism in which shareholders’ interests dominate all others. Corporations operate for the primary purpose of maximizing profits, and returning the highest possible yields to shareholders. In terms of orthodox critiques, we might begin with the assumption that a corporate legal regime attuned to shareholders will produce a number of material benefits for the public at large in their overlapping capacities as investors themselves or employees.  But this, unfortunately, does not appear to be the reality. For one thing, the UK is not a country of widespread capital ownership. Likewise, it is no secret that UK real wages have stagnated over the last decade or so (and, indeed, further back), and this is exacerbated by the ongoing cost of living crisis. Meanwhile, in 2021 dividend distributions climbed back to pre-COVID levels for FTSE 100 firms (£73.7 billion). Since these material benefits do not seem to reach the average citizen, one might reasonably wonder how shareholder capitalism is exactly improving social welfare in Britain today. 

We could also critique another of shareholder capitalism’s assumptions about executive compensation from an orthodox perspective. The logic goes that, because shareholder wealth maximization is the most socio-economically desirable end to corporate governance (which is highly debatable), corporate managers ought to be incentivized in line with the wishes of the general meeting, and the capital markets more broadly. By wedding executive pay packets to share price performance, corporate managers have a compelling incentive to work hard and do a good job. If they do not, they can be removed by a simple majority vote, or they otherwise risk the prospect of a takeover, which may well also result in their removal from office further downstream. Whilst this arrangement incentivizes corporate managers, it also discourages them from shirking their duties, or engaging in self-enrichment, at the corporation’s expense. However, recurring episodes of corporate misconduct indicate that tying executive compensation to share price performance creates a pathway to achieving great personal wealth. For this reason, it should not be surprising when corporate managers are implicated in severe fraud, financial malpractice and brazen accounting manipulation. The recent Patisserie Valerie and Carillion scandals are garden-variety illustrations highlighting that this attendant dimension of shareholder capital does not necessarily function in the envisioned manner, and it has an exacting social cost. 

The Root Problem

These orthodox critiques of shareholder capitalism are adequate and reasonable, insofar as they are consistent with the internal lexicon and modes of thinking that corporate governance commentators typically rely upon when they engage with each other. However, the internal lexicon and modes of thinking have intrinsic limitations. These limitations are borne out of the law and economics movement, a movement that has maintained an assertive chokehold on corporate governance scholarship (and policymaking) for many years. A result of the law and economics movement’s influence on the discipline is that, whilst other academic fields have advanced, the study of corporate governance remains, to a greater or lesser extent, static and continues to be driven by antiquated conventions and philosophies. Thus, unless one is prepared to abandon the standard law and economics toolbox, asking certain questions about shareholder capitalism is essentially out-of-bounds. And the trouble, in my view, is that the root problem with shareholder capitalism lies in a deeper conviction that the law and economics movement holds as sacrosanct, which a researcher observing the discipline’s internal lexicon and modes of thinking simply cannot reach in the customary way. 

The root problem is that, although shareholder capitalism is supported by discrete assumptions like those above, its foundations are in a more general – and inaccurate – assessment of human nature. This assessment hinges on caricaturing humans as “rational egoists” with an insatiable appetite to consume and pursue material gains. When this natural state of being is leveraged within competitive market settings and scaled to a population level, it has a certain dynamism and ability to deliver larger and larger accumulations of wealth. This is in the public interest, not least because competition ensures the efficient allocation of societal and natural resources. As Paddy Ireland notes, in the corporate governance context, these “ideas have found expression in the idea that ‘maximising shareholder value’ benefits not only shareholders but society as a whole”. I have already offered a few examples of why we should be skeptical of the shareholder wealth maximization proposition, but these are merely offshoots of a more profound issue. The root problem underpinning the larger system is that it is assumed that this conception of human nature is fixed and has an unalterable, pre- societal and regulatory existence. Here, the best function of law is to harness and track that nature. To borrow from Hans Kelsen, this is the “grundnorm” of shareholder capitalism from which all else flows. 

However, this assessment of human nature was refuted some time ago. In particular, what studies on human evolution reveal is a rather different, more complicated story about us – one that has yet to be absorbed into the corporate governance canon. Utility-seeking egoism is part of the equation, it is true, but evolutionary economics commentators, like Geoffrey Hodgson, demonstrate that this facet of human behavior is only as dominant as our communal codes and principles of morality allow it to be. To be sure, those studying the evolution of human cooperation, such as Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis, show that law and legal institutions can serve as cues for cultivating equally important facets of human behavior, like goodwill, mutual trust, reciprocity and solidarity. This is not to say that self-interest is somehow absent, but rather that “other-regarding” motivations and preferences can become dominant in the right institutional environments. In other words, law matters. It is a principal driver dictating how humans behave within society, including within substructures like capital markets and corporations.

What can be distilled from this is that law and legal institutions can either be used to promote self-interest and what the German economist Goetz Briefs described as “marginal ethics”, or something else. Ultimately, how capitalism, and by extension the corporation, functions is a political and legal choice, not an inescapable conclusion arising from our nature as a species. Granted, much of the root problem is obscured by the neo-liberal “political project” that David Harvey details, of which the law and economics movement is a part. However, as alluded to by Susan Strange, the current corporate capitalism in operation in the UK, and more globally, exists “under the authority of and by permission of the state” and is “conducted on whatever terms the state may choose to dictate, or allow”. E. P. Thompson was, therefore, right when he opined that human beings do not behave like rational egoists, striving to improve their positions at others’ expense, because the human condition is immutable and cannot be re-directed to more appropriate ends. Human beings behave this way because of socio-legal institutional signals.

The Classical Legal Tradition 

This is where the classical legal tradition comes into play. Put plainly, should the state allow this formulation of corporate capitalism – and all the societal and environmental hazards that go hand-in-hand with it – to subsist? More to the point, should the function of law and legal institutions be reduced to stimulating the expression of humanity’s most destructive traits instead of its best ones? The classical legal tradition takes a view on these questions, and in that sense it positions us to understand why reforms are actually necessary. Reforms are not needed because shareholder capitalism has the wrong idea about how to tabulate and achieve aggregate utility, as counter narratives like stakeholder capitalism would have us believe. It is because the proper function of law and legal institutions is to promote the common good, and the legitimate exercise of public authority is contingent on upholding and furthering it. The Thomistic tradition further specifies that the common good is not achievable at all unless policymakers take care in orientating citizens to a community of civic friendship with each other. 

Although developments in our understanding of human evolution in group settings confirm that we are capable of cultivating things like mutual trust and solidarity (even in market settings), this does not seem possible where the state has institutionalized a set of prescriptions for provoking what Oliver Williamson referred to as “self-interest seeking with guile”. That is to say, policymakers have made a collective choice to opt for lax corporate governance rules and ethical norms that condition and encourage people to bend or avoid societal and environmental obligations if it generates market or material advantage. From a classical perspective, such arrangements cannot be regarded as legally genuine and valid. They are frauds or imposters, and more like acts of violence than “law” properly construed. They indicate that political authorities have lost touch with what the common good means; what the purpose of law is – this is why reforms are necessary.

In the second instalment of this two-part contribution, I offer a preliminary sketch of what corporate capitalism would look like in the UK if it was more closely anchored in the classical legal tradition, with particular attention paid to the tradition’s controlling principle that policymakers have a duty and corresponding authority to promote the flourishing of all members of the community. 

J.S. Liptrap


[1] Note that this is not the first occasion that Ius & Iustitium has featured an essay on the corporation and the common good.

A tort for “cancel culture”

In his annual address to the Vatican diplomatic corps on January 11, Pope Francis decried the phenomenon of “cancel culture.” The Pope noted that “[u]nder the guise of defending diversity,” “cancel culture” obliterates “all sense of identity, with the risk of silencing positions that defend a respectful and balanced understanding of all sensibilities.” Worse than that, it promotes a kind of thinking that is “constrained to deny history or, worse yet, to rewrite it in terms of present-day categories, whereas any historical situation must be interpreted in the light of a hermeneutics of that particular time, not that of today.” 

One finds examples of the “cancel culture” condemned by the Pope everywhere, with new examples emerging almost daily. Professors and podcasters alike find themselves in the hot seat with astonishing regularity. However, few solutions to “cancel culture” have been identified. The cycle continues. Some prominent professor, executive, or personality says something wicked, foolish, or merely unpopular. The usual suspects of left-wing journalists and Twitter power users find it and boost the signal, often notifying the person’s employer through the phenomenon of “snitch tagging.” The outrage builds in a sort of positive feedback loop. Finally the desired goal is reached and the professor or executive finds herself without a job, without friends, and without prospects. 

Continue reading “A tort for “cancel culture””

Catholics for Choice and Trademark law

On the evening of January 21, 2022, the night before the annual March for Life in Washington, D.C., pro-life activists gathered in the Basilica of the National Shrine of the Immaculate Conception to celebrate Mass for the unborn and for the success of the March. Unbeknownst to the Mass-goers, another group of protesters gathered with a projector across the street from the Basilica. As Mass was being celebrated inside the church, these protestors projected onto the outside of the church statements in support of legal abortion access. This group was led by Catholics for Choice, an organization dedicated to protecting legal abortion.

The same group released a statement that evening by its president Jamie L. Manson stating, “I support abortion access because my Catholic faith teaches that healthcare is a human right, and that includes abortion. … Catholics for Choice will never stop shining our light on behalf of the pro-choice, faithful majority for the fundamental constitutional and human right to abortion – as a matter of justice, a matter of freedom, and a matter of faith.” The following day Wilton Cardinal Gregory made plain his view of the dissident group and their stunt, stating, “The true voice of the Church was only found within the Basilica,” and that “those whose antics projected words on the outside of the church building demonstrated by those pranks that they really are external to the Church and they did so at night.” He then cited John 13:30: “And Judas having received the bread, went out immediately. And it was night.”

Continue reading “Catholics for Choice and Trademark law”

Customary Law and Popular Sovereignty

Following are lightly edited remarks delivered at a panel on “Unwritten Law,” held at the annual meeting of the Association of American Law Schools on January 6, 2022. These informal remarks are of course not intended to be rigorous or comprehensive, merely suggestive. Many thanks to organizer Robert Leider and fellow panelists Jeremy Waldron, Steve Sachs and Ashraf Ahmed for their thoughts and contributions.


It’s difficult to know how to discuss the topic of unwritten law in twelve minutes. The topic is an incredibly heterogeneous one, full of analytic complications that require endless preliminary distinctions, such as the extremely pellucid and not at all confusing distinction, beloved of legal historians, between legal custom and customary law. So naturally I propose simply to heroically ignore all those conceptual preliminaries and tell you how I changed my mind on a fundamental substantive issue: the relationship between popular sovereignty and custom. 

Continue reading “Customary Law and Popular Sovereignty”

The Private Right of Action

Recently Texas enacted the Heartbeat Bill, which contains a twist on the standard heartbeat law, which many states have adopted in recent years. It allows individuals to sue abortion providers who violate the law, entitling them to collect at least $10,000. (It does not allow individuals to sue women who obtain abortions, however.) The United States Supreme Court declined to enjoin the enforcement of the law on a complicated procedural basis, but it is certain that there will be more litigation over the Heartbeat Bill. In fact, President Joseph Biden and Attorney General Merrick Garland have, citing the sanctity of the 1973 United States Supreme Court decision Roe v. Wade, vowed to prevent Texas from enforcing the law. President Biden has even considered taking other, more direct action to circumvent the law.

Continue reading “The Private Right of Action”

Justinian Goes Fox Hunting

Perhaps without realizing it, most United States-educated lawyers are familiar with Book II.1.13 of Justinian’s Institutes. Here is the relevant excerpt:

Does an animal become yours when it is wounded and ready to be caught? Some jurists thought it became yours at once and stayed yours till you gave up the chase, only then becoming available again to the next taker. Others thought that it became yours only when you caught it. We confirm that view. After all, many things can happen to stop you catching the animal.

This passage is referenced in Pierson v. Post, a New York case from 1805 that most American law students read in their first-year property law course. Pierson v. Post involved a dispute between two hunters over who was the rightful owner of a fox killed on a beach on Long Island: The hunter who first spotted and pursued the fox? Or the hunter who intercepted, captured, and killed the fox? Apart from its usefulness in introducing law students to the complexities of property rights, Pierson v. Post undoubtedly owes its place in the first-year law curriculum to its amusingly old-timey facts (a fox hunt in Long Island!) and the playfully flowery prose employed in the opinions, particularly the dissent (“[W]ho would keep a pack of hounds; or what gentleman, at the sound of the horn, and at peep of day, would mount his steed, and for hours together, ‘sub jove frigido,’ or a vertical sun, pursue the windings of this wily quadruped, if, just as night came on, and his stratagems and strength were nearly exhausted, a saucy intruder, who had not shared in the honors or labors of the chase, were permitted to come in at the death, and bear away in triumph the object of pursuit?”)

Continue reading “Justinian Goes Fox Hunting”

DACA and Leadership

In Department of Homeland Security v. Regents of the University of California, 591 U.S. ____ (2020), Chief Justice John Roberts struck down the actions of the Department of Homeland Security revoking the prior administrative actions popularly known as “DACA” (“Deferred Action  for Childhood Arrivals”). The DACA program, established in 2012 and expanded in 2014, allows individuals who came to the United States illegally as children to defer their deportation and, having done so, regularize their immigration status. The program came to include access to benefits. Shortly after President Trump took office in 2017, the Department of Homeland Security rescinded its DACA orders. The Supreme Court struck down these rescissions, not as exceeding the government’s power, but as failing to comply perfectly with the Administrative Procedure Act.

Continue reading “DACA and Leadership”

Against Judicial Dyarchy

Ius & Iustitium is happy to present this guest post by Jamie McGowan. Jamie McGowan is a postgraduate researcher in Constitutional Law at the University of Glasgow.


The recent debate about originalism in the US has triggered a lot of conversation about judicial deference. Adrian Vermeule recently clarified that the position of common good constitutionalism is that legislators of every kind ought to consider the common good and natural law when making legislative decisions. He rightly noted, however, that a very different question arises concerning the “institutional allocation” of that legislative power. Given the recent Bostock decision in the US, the question that inevitably enters the conservative legal debate is whether it is wise to allocate so much legislative power in the judiciary. In civil law countries, the judiciary deals mostly in the particularia of individual cases, determining moral right in its context, without establishing legal precedent. In most modern common law countries, however, an incredible amount of binding legislative power is bestowed upon judges, to the extent that the judiciary becomes a sort of supra-legislature. In classical legal theory, where law carries a telos of upholding the common good, the pertinent question is whether this judicial supremacy is friend or foe to the primacy of the common good and, by implication, the natural law.

Continue reading “Against Judicial Dyarchy”

The Significance of Roman Law for the Development of European Law

by Wolfgang Waldstein[1]

The Roman jurists, quite matter-of-factly, recognized natural law to be an inherent normative order for mankind, recognizable through reason and, thus, applied it in concrete decisions. With this work, the Roman jurists developed a concrete knowledge regarding the practice of natural law, thereby making it a historic reality. Over time, the deviations from natural law, which existed in the old Roman law, were perceived more and more as being unjust. Through countless individual decisions, these were corrected by the Roman jurists, in order to be able to arrive at just decisions. This work by the Roman jurists was conducted over a time period of nearly 500 years, from the 2nd century BC to the 3rd century AD. As was mentioned in the introduction, the results of this work were published in the year 533 AD by Emperor Justinian as one of his codes of law, in a work known as the Digest. The rediscovery of this work in the Middle Ages and the study of it at the original academy of the artes in Bologna, resulted in this school’s becoming the very first university in Europe. This university then influenced the entire further development of legal culture in Europe. Upon this foundation, the “natural law codes ”, the General Prussian state law of 1794 (AL), the Napoleonic Code of 1804, and the 1811 Civil Code of Austria (ABGB) were created. Based on this, the ABGB, even today, can say in § 16: “Every person has innate rights, already intelligible through reason.”

Continue reading “The Significance of Roman Law for the Development of European Law”