Man Is Known by the Company He Keeps: Corporate Law and the Common Good

Ius et Iustitium is happy to present this guest post by Gregory B.L. Chilson. Mr. Chilson is an LL.M. candidate at the University of Vienna.


In his examination of American patent law for Ius & Iustitium earlier this year, Jake Neu’s piece explored Adrian Vermeule’s view that the common good tradition enjoys a pedigree worthy of greater examination. Neu offered a compelling demonstration of the practical role which the classical legal tradition can and should play in contemporary jurisprudence, drawing on his chosen topic of patent law. Can the same be said of the company and corporate law as well?

Just as the patent found its role in Venetian courts, the parentage for our companies can be traced back to late medieval Italy. Although the modern company is often attributed to English and Dutch Mercantilism (and French liberalism)[1], jurists ought not overlook the extent to which English guilds were in part influenced by Italian confraternities and para-ecclesiastical bodies.[2] The term ‘guild’ itself, is well noted for its dual meaning as it is a derivative of the Germanic word ‘geld’ which first and foremost as a verb means ‘to pay’ or ‘contribute’, but also as a noun for ‘sacrifice’ or ‘worship’.[3]

Both meanings point to a common theme: pulling resources together in order to achieve common goals, both religious and secular in character, which were desired by stakeholders and at the same time benefitted the society and the state.

Continue reading “Man Is Known by the Company He Keeps: Corporate Law and the Common Good”

Copyright, Author’s Right, and the Common Good: Fair Use (Part II)

Ius et Iustitium is happy to present this guest post by Jake Neu. Mr. Neu is a partner at Bradley Arant Boult Cummings LLP. This is the second part of a two-part series, part I can be found here. Mr. Neu argues in favor of the civil law (or droit d’auteur) understanding of copyright. A reply to this series, countering that the droit d’auteur (and copyright generally) is ill-founded on natural law and Thomistic grounds, will follow.


Defining Fair Use

As introduced in my first post on copyright law, fair use is a peculiarly American legal doctrine that permits the public to copy copyrighted works without payment to the original author in various circumstances. Other Anglo-American jurisdictions have some notion of fair use or fair dealing, but these are typically more limited in scope, nothing like the fact-based flexible inquiry found in the United States. But as I also previewed in the initial post, the flexibility of the inquiry and its increasing scope has also been the source of two concerns. First, there are jurisprudential concerns about fair use exceptions swallowing the grant of copyright. Second, pragmatically, the application of fair use in any given case has become highly unpredictable. In this post, I argue that by introducing to the fair use analysis certain principles from the natural law and common good jurisprudence underlying the Continental conception of author’s right, we may retain the flexibility so advantageous to the American conception of fair use while also providing predictable contours and limiting principles to allay the twin concerns that fair use raises.

Continue reading “Copyright, Author’s Right, and the Common Good: Fair Use (Part II)”

Copyright, Author’s Right, and the Common Good (Part I)

Ius et Iustitium is happy to present this guest post by Jake Neu. Mr. Neu is a partner at Bradley Arant Boult Cummings LLP. This is the first part of a two-part series. Part II is available here. Mr. Neu argues in favor of the civil law (or droit d’auteur) understanding of copyright. A reply to this series, countering that the droit d’auteur (and copyright generally) is ill-founded on natural law and Thomistic grounds, will follow.


In my previous post on “The Common Good in Patent Law,” I stated that modern patent law had a single source, the Venetian Patent Statute of 1474. In that statute one finds all the principal characteristics of modern patent law present in various stages of maturity, and this conception eventually spread to all European countries and around the world. Therefore, patent law enjoys a very stable and common global understanding of its nature and purpose, even if the contours and scope of the law remain hotly debated.

The same cannot be said for copyright law, which has long struggled to balance two competing, ancient conceptions of what copyright law should be and do. Given the importance that copyright plays in technology, software, data management, and mass entertainment today, these differences have profound implications for how we organize rights and obligations under the law. Before considering how copyright may operate in support of the common good, we must first discuss these competing conceptions.

Continue reading “Copyright, Author’s Right, and the Common Good (Part I)”

Imperare aude! Dare to command! (Part II)

Ius & Iustitium is pleased to present this guest post by Ricardo Calleja, lecturer in ethics at the University of Navarre. This is the second and final part. The first part may be found here.


At the risk of repeating some ideas, let me clarify why a call to exercise authority, including forceful coercion, does not foster or endorse arbitrariness, authoritarianism, or decisionism.

Arbitrariness

Arbitrariness, in our modern language, is the condition of decisions based on “random choice or personal whim, rather than any reason or system,” and the characteristic of “power or a ruling body unrestrained and autocratic in the use of authority” (Oxford Dictionary).

Imperare aude, the call to command, is not a call to arbitrariness. For the act of the will to be rational, the acts of consilium and iuditium must precede that of imperium. These acts contain the informative and evaluative deliberations that seem to us more obviously to be acts of reason. However, as I have discussed in Part I, imperare is itself also an act of reason because reason commands the intention to certain goods as ends and the will to act accordingly. Hence, random choice or personal whim ought not be the grounds or motivations for any decision by an authority. An arbitrary decision is contrary to the proper exercise of imperium.

Continue reading “Imperare aude! Dare to command! (Part II)”

Imperare aude! Dare to command! (Part I)

Ius & Iustitium is pleased to present this guest post by Ricardo Calleja, lecturer in ethics at the University of Navarre. This is the first part in a series. The second part may be found here.


“Enlightenment is man’s emergence from his self-imposed nonage. Nonage is the inability to use one’s own understanding without another’s guidance. This nonage is self-imposed if its cause lies not in lack of understanding but in indecision and lack of courage to use one’s own mind without another’s guidance. Dare to know! Sapere aude! ‘Have the courage to use your own understanding,’ is therefore the motto of the enlightenment.” (Kant, What is Enlightenment?).

The project of the Enlightenment can be summed up as the rejection of authority. In particular, the mediating role of authorities in conveying truths, theoretical or practical, to adult individuals is discarded. Everyone must think for themselves — must dare do think for themselves. Sapere aude! Consequently, authority no longer finds its foundation in truth and reason but can only build on consent and will, and can only justify its choices in terms of instrumental reasons. As Pierre Manent has recently underlined in a masterful new book, the modern attempt to reduce authority to the role of merely protecting individual rights — conceived as the freedom to satisfy infinite desires — ultimately has led to a debasement of all social institutions: familial, academic, ecclesiastical, and civil. The upshot is that the philosophical principle of the Enlightenment deforms the character of rulers and ruled alike, making the former irresolute and the latter undisciplined.

The modern project might have helped to open spaces for individual freedom and participation in action for the common good by transforming those social structures of the pre-modern world that were not responsive to the demands of some of the core principles of the classical legal tradition. Instead, it has eroded the individual and social capacity to exercise practical reason — particularly when acting in common — by blocking our responses to the commands of natural law. We are left with instrumental reasons at the service of purely subjective preferences, making any practical pursuit of the common good not only impossible, but unthinkable. 

Continue reading “Imperare aude! Dare to command! (Part I)”

Common-Good Constitutionalism and the “Ius Constitutionale Commune” in Latin America

Ius & Iustitium is pleased to present this guest post by José Ignacio Hernández G. Professor Hernández is professor of administrative law at “Andrés Bello” Catholic University and Central University, Venezuela, invited professor at Castillo-La Mancha University, Spain, and a fellow of the Growth Lab at Harvard Kennedy School.


Originalism, the dominant mode of legal interpretation in American constitutional law, posits that the interpretation of the U.S. Constitution must be according to its “original” public meaning, that is, the meaning as it was in 1789. In an article published in The Atlantic earlier this year, Adrian Vermeule proposes a different methodology, based on the common good, which proposes that the Constitution be interpreted in accordance with the classical legal tradition, with the final goal of promoting common goods. In other words, instead of the text, the polestar of common-good constitutionalism is purposive ordering to certain social ends. According to Vermeule, common-good constitutionalism draws “upon an immemorial tradition that includes, in addition to positive law, sources such as the ius gentium—the law of nations or the “general law” common to all civilized legal systems—and principles of objective natural morality, including legal morality in the sense used by the American legal theorist Lon Fuller: the inner logic that the activity of law should follow in order to function well as law.” 

Continue reading “Common-Good Constitutionalism and the “Ius Constitutionale Commune” in Latin America”

Canon Law and Political Discourse: What the Church Can and Must Offer Politics

Ius & Iustitium is happy to present this guest post by Rev. James Bradley, J.C.D. Rev. Bradley is Assistant Professor of Canon Law at The Catholic University of America, Washington, D.C.


Three months out from the U.S. presidential election, one in which two of the four prospective presidential and vice-presidential candidates were baptized in the Catholic Church, we inevitably hear again the same old criticism of religious involvement in political life. There is nothing new under the sun. Yet as attention is focused more and more on the election, from the perspective of the Catholic Church’s polity and law, and thus also its interaction with the political and social order of the civil society, revisiting and re-presenting the whys and wherefores of ecclesiastical involvement in political discourse is perhaps a helpful exercise for Catholics and non-Catholics alike. I want to do this briefly from a juridical perspective based on the Catholic Church’s legal system: her canon law. My purpose is not to prove a point, per se, but to demonstrate in simple terms why the Catholic Church involves herself in political discourse, under what terms she does this, and why this cannot be simply and uncritically dismissed.

Continue reading “Canon Law and Political Discourse: What the Church Can and Must Offer Politics”

Ius & Iustitium has streamlined its submission process

Until now, the submission process for Ius & Iustitium has involved contacting an editor, either here or at The Josias, or a previous contributor, with a pitch or a draft essay. We have received (and published) some really excellent submissions. Candidly, however, the process has been a little inefficient—both for authors and editors. To streamline things, Ius & Iustitium has implemented a contact form, the link to which may be found here, as well as in the upper right hand of the homepage. We welcome intelligent contributions from within the classical legal tradition. Editors will review all submissions through the contact form and respond as promptly as possible. We also welcome responses to published pieces, notes of appreciation, critiques, queries, and whatever else our readers might submit.

A word about style: Ius & Iustitium does not have a complicated house style. Acknowledging the range of sources our contributors draw upon, it would be impossible to cover each and every question. Additionally, there is no requirement that submissions be heavily footnoted or contain links to every source. However, authors should try to conform to a few general guidelines:

  • A brief note requires less support than a lengthy essay.
  • Ius & Iustitium has an audience of readers interested in questions of jurisprudence and politics—in many cases these readers will want to read your sources.
  • Ius & Iustitium does not publish briefs, motions, or law review articles: One need not write in a highly formal style, but excessive informality hampers your argument.
  • Personal attacks may be effective on Twitter, but Ius & Iustitium is not Twitter.
  • Selections in Latin (or any other foreign language) should also be translated.
  • Very lengthy contributions may be broken up into a series of posts: If you submit a lengthy contribution, it is helpful to indicate how best it might be divided.

The Editors

Murder, Parking Tickets, and the Natural Law

Ius et Iustitium is happy to present this post by Patrick Button. Mr. Button is an attorney in Orlando, Florida.


Usually when the natural law is brought up in mainstream discourse on law and morality, when it is brought up at all, it is in one of two contexts. First, the legitimacy of disobeying unjust laws, and second, debates over so-called morals legislation aimed against carnal vices. These are certainly areas where the relationship between natural law and positive law is of great importance, but the scope of that relationship is much broader. In truth, all just legislation is derived from the natural law, from the prohibition of murder to parking regulations. One might reasonably object that parking regulations are relatively arbitrary, and do not seem comparable to laws against specific and grave evils like murder. In fact there is a categorical distinction to be made, which St. Thomas explains in Question 95 of Part I-II of the Summa Theologiae. 

Continue reading “Murder, Parking Tickets, and the Natural Law”

The Deconstructionist Ghost in the Textualist Machine

Ius et Iustitium is happy to present this guest post by Vincent Clarke. Mr. Clarke is scholar of Lacanian psychoanalysis.


It is not often commented on, but judicial textualism bears many of the same hallmarks as philosophical postmodernism. When this is properly appreciated, many of the results of textualist legal reasoning can be better understood. Implicit in textualism are many of the same principles as postmodernism. Understood in this way, textualism operates as a sort of system of gears allowing postmodern culture to infiltrate the legal apparatus. That the founders of textualism may not have intended such a result is an historical irony, but does not change the ultimate result. Since postmodernism’s aim is ultimately to undermine the legal system, textualism thus becomes an instrument of subversion.

These questions have been brought into much sharper focus with the recent ruling in Bostock v. Clayton County, 140 S. Ct. 1731 (2020), where the Supreme Court expanded the protections offered in the Civil Rights Act of 1964 to include not just discrimination based on race, color, religion, sex or national origin, but also ‘gender identity’ and ‘sexual orientation.’

Continue reading “The Deconstructionist Ghost in the Textualist Machine”

Ius et Iustitium is happy to present this guest post by Vincent Clarke. Mr. Clarke is scholar of Lacanian psychoanalysis.


It is not often commented on, but judicial textualism bears many of the same hallmarks as philosophical postmodernism. When this is properly appreciated, many of the results of textualist legal reasoning can be better understood. Implicit in textualism are many of the same principles as postmodernism. Understood in this way, textualism operates as a sort of system of gears allowing postmodern culture to infiltrate the legal apparatus. That the founders of textualism may not have intended such a result is an historical irony, but does not change the ultimate result. Since postmodernism’s aim is ultimately to undermine the legal system, textualism thus becomes an instrument of subversion.

These questions have been brought into much sharper focus with the recent ruling in Bostock v. Clayton County, 140 S. Ct. 1731 (2020), where the Supreme Court expanded the protections offered in the Civil Rights Act of 1964 to include not just discrimination based on race, color, religion, sex or national origin, but also ‘gender identity’ and ‘sexual orientation.’

Continue reading “The Deconstructionist Ghost in the Textualist Machine”